Bad ideas: Time banks

The idea behind a time bank is pretty simple: instead of being paid in money you get paid in time credits—1 minute for every minute of labour that you do. Here is what psychologist Tim Kasser has to say about them in The high price of materialism (a pretty good book, all things considered):

"…people donate a number of hours of their services and then receive an equal number of hours of others’ services in return; in such systems, the work of a lawyer is considered equal in value to that of a gardener…[time banks] work to support neighbours, are egalitarian in their sense of what people’s time in worth, and are rarely used in ways that have harmful social and environmental costs. ('The High Price of Materialism' pg. 114)"

This strikes me as incorrect. Time banks must have substantial social harms. People’s time is worth different amounts, and this is both necessary and morally acceptable. To illustrate, let’s take the example above—lawyers and gardeners.

To become a lawyer one must first qualify for expensive law school by being an outstanding candidate. Once there you must invest 3-5 years of your life learning very difficult subject matter in order to become qualified. As a junior lawyer you aren’t very good at your job. As such, most firms pay you very little while you are on so-called ‘probation’. A graduate lawyer at Ashhurst makes $80 000 or thereabouts. That is a substantial sum. But they work 60+ hours per week for at least 50 weeks a year. That works out to $26 per hour. I used to make that working the check-in desks for cruise liners. Once you’ve cut your teeth and proven you are an asset to the firm you receive a substantial pay increase (this is long before making it to partner), but this is still to somewhere in the order of $35 per hour. The big bucks don’t start rolling until you are a partner with two decades or experience and proven skills that are marketable and billable.

Meanwhile, a gardener needs no qualifications and must invest only a small amount of capital to get started. Their wage is based almost entirely on their physical labour and has very little to do with inherent ability. From the get go they earn about $20 an hour and quickly work their way up to maybe $25. Once there they need to start a business and get employees in order to earn more.
So what’s wrong with treating their work equally, as time banks do?

It’s a problem of incentives. If lawyers earn the same as gardeners, why would anyone become qualified as a lawyer? Why pay the extra cost of tuition and put in the extra effort of study when you can earn the same as a gardener immediately? Citizens in a time banking society would specialise overwhelming in jobs requiring little to no investment in skills and would avoid high effort jobs. Yet it is precisely these jobs that we increasingly need as we become technologically advanced—doctors, engineers, mechanics, teachers etc.

Another problem is that time is a very imprecise way to measure the value of a thing. What about jobs that require a lot of time but little effort vs. jobs that require a lot of effort but not much time? Is minding a car park for an hour worth the same as performing a 15 minute piece of eye surgery? How can you effectively differentiate between the values of these tasks if you pay in time?

High wages don’t exist by mistake. They are overwhelming a reward for earlier investments of effort, time and money. They reflect higher levels of productivity resulting from higher levels of education and innate ability. Certainly there are some unjust elements to wages, but on average they reflect necessary incentives for getting people to skill up in areas where there is demand and to encourage high ability people into jobs that are especially taxing that only they can handle. If you act as though everything is worth the same amount, then people will not invest in things that are actually more expensive, whether in terms of cash or effort. Pretending things are worth the same doesn’t make it true.

A more technical problem with time banks is that they rely on the labour theory of value, which is a problematic theory. The labour theory of value is that the worth of some item is (or ought to be, some Marxists would argue) a reflection of the amount of labour that went into it. 

This is incorrect. Indeed, the market theory of value, where the worth of an item is determined by its supply and demand for it in a market, superseded the labour theory of value precisely because it answers puzzles that the labour theory of demand cannot. Let’s examine two issues. First, let’s imagine a man who really enjoys making wheels but is of only modest skill. He spends two months making a wheel. He then takes it to market and demands the equivalent of two month’s wages for it. Buyers in the market laugh and purchase wheels for the equivalent of an hour’s wages from the wheel factory. It would seem that the labour theory of value is completely invalidated. Something is only ‘worth’ what people are willing to pay for it.

Consider another case, that of the thirsty man in a dessert. How much do you think he would be willing to pay for a diamond? Almost nothing, because he doesn’t need a diamond, and the chances of him being able to sell one before he dies of thirst is very slim. Given his limited budget of time (and money) he should not waste it haggling over a diamond. How much do you think he would be willing to pay for water? A lot given that he will die without it. How much will it cost? There isn’t much water around, so it is probably very precious to everyone nearby. Here we see the emergence of supply and demand. There is a supply of diamonds but no demand; and demand for water but limited supply. The value of the diamond will be low while the value of water is high. This is despite the fact that mining diamonds is hard and time consuming while tapping an oasis or aquifer is relatively quick and easy.

The time bank uses the labour theory of value to identify the worth of some service and in doing so inefficiently distributes that service. Not only will nobody become a doctor in a time banking society but everyone will want a doctor’s time because it is relatively cheap. In exchange for an hour working as an adventure tour guide I can get cosmetic surgery. There will consequently be an undersupply of medical services and an excess of spare time wanting to be spent on medical services. This is an inefficient situation. The market for medical services cannot clear unless the time-cost of such services rises. But the cost of the medical service can only rise if the time-value of the doctor’s services is given a premium above the time-value of the gardener’s services. This is exactly what we do when we pay doctors more than gardeners. Money can be exchanged for any service, and doctor’s services are worth more than gardener’s services. Now we are right back at ‘market ideology’.

One might here argue, as many Marxists do, that the market value might be efficient, but it is not ‘fair’. But isn’t it perfectly good and just that the person who wants something the most must pay the most for it? I challenge you to design a fairer way of rationing goods. The Marxists said ‘from each according to his ability, to each according to his need’. But here we again run into the incentive problem outlined above. Why would someone with high ability bother to demonstrate that ability if it meant more work and yet the same reward? The experience of communism bears out these theoretical propositions. Eastern Europe under communism was characterised by mass idleness.

Moreover, is it not perfectly fair and just that someone who has to put more effort into their work is rewarded more substantially than someone whose work requires less effort? What the size of this discrepancy ‘ought’ to be is difficult to estimate, but that is a valid argument for simply divesting this decision to market forces. Where this results in gross differences, as in some executive salaries, we can intervene post-market with taxation and the like. This is a far cry from the market intervention intrinsic to time banks.  

This all reminds me of the time I went to the launch of a book called ‘A world without money’. I mentioned it to an economist friend of mine and she said ‘I imagine it would look a lot like a world with money’. Market mechanisms and their paraphernalia—notably currency—emerged organically and are the best tool we have for a managing a wide range of issues. They are not unfair, they are effective. What’s unfair is the accident of birth, and we can correct for that, through public education and health, for example, without needing to get rid of the market.

Comments