Perhaps the most fundamental concept in economics is
utility. Individuals seek to maximise their utility, firms, governments and
other actors respond by providing the goods that give people utility, and the
economy emerges as a natural consequence. Yet utility remains a rather
under-investigated concept. There are good reasons for this. Having utility as
a black box allows us to treat it as entirely subjective; this allows economics
to retain its amoral character. However, it also encourages economists to focus
almost entirely on GDP growth as the source of higher utility and this has come
to be an increasingly untenable
assumption of late.
Multiple streams of inquiry, notably those around the
Easterlin paradox and the Genuine Progress Indicator, have noted that
subjective wellbeing does not increase markedly above a certain level of
income. Stated more formally, there are diminishing returns to utility from
income. Graphically, this would look something like the following:
While the impact of GDP growth on utility from
consumption is diminishing its impact on other factors is increasing.
Environmental pressure from greater fossil fuel use, resource intensity and
population growth is coming up against planetary boundaries. In the future,
sources of GDP growth that derive from increases in economics throughput will
be untenable. Unfortunately, historically GDP growth has tended to parallel
increases in throughput. Moving to a system focused on increases in
productivity rather than increases in GDP will be difficult and require a
change in thinking.
Some scholars working on the so-called ‘Genuine Progress
Indicator’ have suggested that what is required is an emphasis on development rather than growth. They propose that we need some
way to measure human progress that is not predicated on increases in
throughput. It is here that a richer understanding of utility becomes critical.
If we can determine a way of increasing utility that do not revolve around the
consumption of physical goods then we can ‘develop’ without growing.
It seems to me that if we want to build such a model we
need to unite three separate streams of inquiry from economics, psychology and
philosophy. Thus far these three have operated in siloed discursive spaces, to
the detriment of each. Philosophy has largely ignored the importance of
happiness and focused instead on meaning and virtue. Economics has focused, as
already discussed, almost entirely on the physical determinants of life
satisfaction. And psychology has devoted its efforts predominantly to happiness
in the ecstatic (that is fleeting) sense rather than trying to model a ‘good
life’ (though psychiatry has made some inroads at times—see Victor Frankel).
I propose a preliminary model of the following form:
Utilityi = Wellbeingi + Happinessi + Meaningi
The three variables—wellbeing, happiness and meaning—correspond
approximately to the determinants each discipline has focussed on to date. That
is to say, ‘wellbeing captures, for the most part, those determinants of
utility that economics has traditionally focused on and which are improved by
income growth. Things like food, water, shelter etc. ‘Happiness’ collects those
determinants of utility traditionally investigated by psychology. And ‘meaning’
refers to those determinants traditionally investigated by philosophy.
This is a regression model, which I think is very important.
Thus far we tended to focus on individual predictors of happiness in isolation.
For example, we have studies (sometimes experimental for good identification)
of things like achievement, companionship and money, but we don’t, as far as I
know, have much in the way of regression models establishing the relative
effect on happiness of all of these
variables taken together. That is to say which don’t know which ones are
most important or have the strongest effects. We don’t really know how they
interact or whether their effects are linear, among other things. This means
that if we were to guide public policy along these lines we wouldn’t know how
to weight each factor, which would lead to enormous inefficiency. A regression
estimate would correct, at least to some extent, this issue.
At this stage I have only very preliminary thoughts on what
might be contained under each heading. Wellbeing can be approached formally
through Maslow’s hierarchy of human needs and we can use traditional economic
variables to measure it. Income is a good aggregate proxy because it enables
higher quality food, water, clothing, shelter and even access to sex (though
not reproduction or love, which are perhaps more important). The other two
blocks—happiness and meaning—are not necessarily more difficult to approach
formally but they are more difficult to find variables for. This is, I think,
one of the strongest reasons why we have tended, in public policy at least, to
focus on income growth as an indicator of progress—it is easy to measure.
I have written about happiness in a previous post. The
core of the difficulty is that happiness is fleeting by definition, so we need
time series models and high frequency data. It is no good discovering that
heroin use leads to increased happiness if we can’t see that this happiness
only lasts three hours and turns to unhappiness in the long run. It is also no
good noting that silver medallists aren’t happy at the time they come second if
we don’t observe that their training period was immensely purposeful and gave
them a great deal of satisfaction, for example.
Meaning is not quite so hard. In the four thousand odd
years of philosophical writings on utility we have some themes that can be
approached with variables—love, family, religious connection, community
engagements, among others. What is very difficult is capturing psychic health
in the psychiatric sense. Someone with mental health problems of the chemical
variety might be obvious in the data (there may even be an appropriate
indicator variable) but someone who is merely highly neurotic (in the manner of
Nietzsche, for example) will not show up. What is somewhat less difficult is
measuring the determinants of meaning identified by the existentialist
philosophers of the mid-twentieth century. Expressed in an extremely simplistic
form, their philosophy is that life will be experienced as meaningful if an
individual is able to satisfy their authentic preferences. What is meant by
authentic is that the preferences are indeed the individual’s—they are not
following the preferences of someone else, such as parents or the community, in
bad faith and hoping for a good outcome nonetheless.
I have written about this particular problem in another post as well. What’s key and what has not been done satisfactorily in the past
to my knowledge is the simultaneous investigation of preferences, life
circumstances and utility outcomes. Utility has only ever been investigated
against either preferences or life circumstances. But that is not what the
theory from philosophy would suggest is important. A second, more technical,
issue is that identifying preferences is tricky. It is especially tricky to
identify complex preferences (such as for a career as an international trade
lawyer rather than merely a career) and preferential trade-offs (such as for
family or career) from data.
So this is where I am at right now. My PhD will basically
involve building up this model as far as I can in three years or so. Thoughts
and comments from people greatly appreciated
Comments
Post a Comment