The discipline of economics is frequently criticised for
using too much mathematics, for giving precedence and undue reverence to highly
mathematical models, and for looking down on social sciences that don’t utilise
mathematics as it does. I’d like to chime in to this debate. There are some
compelling arguments on both sides. I’ll try to be brief.
‘The other day in The
Canberra Times some guy was
complaining that “there are too many equations in economics”. That’s
ridiculous. Can you imagine someone saying “There are too many equations in air
traffic control…we would get better outcomes if we used fewer equations in air
traffic control.”? You can’t, because it’s ridiculous.’
There are numerous situations in research and practice
where you need numbers to get a deep understanding of something. You can’t
determine the estimated time of arrival of a plane without mathematics.
Similarly, you can’t give a compelling estimate of how much more money
Australia’s tertiary education sector ‘ought’ to receive without a mathematical
model of things like the costs and benefits of tertiary education compared to
other potential recipients of government money or untaxed income.
You also need maths to engage in the empirical
verification of hypotheses. This is very important. Without tests we have no
knowledge, and without knowledge might
makes right or rhetoric makes right,
neither of which is a great outcome. Verification requires tests, and good
tests require data—reams of it. Statistical tools become a necessity, and statistics
is a branch of mathematics. This is especially true in the social sciences,
where the inability to bring about controlled conditions in a lab means large
samples and advanced identification techniques are critical for getting precise
results. The process of verification is expedited if hypotheses arrive at the
statistician’s table already in a mathematical form, so economists tend to put
ideas into such forms early in their lifecycles.
However, while empirical verification of hypotheses is
the essence of the scientific method (see Karl Popper) and maths is required
for empirics, economists sometimes skip a step and think the essence of science
is just maths. Thus calculus, set theory and the other branches of mathematics
frequently employed by economics are sometimes utilised seemingly for their own
sake.
One example passed to me from a friend: his lecturer
spent nearly half an hour proving that utility curves are thin, because
otherwise they various arcane mathematical assumptions required for sketching
them graphically would be violated. Nobody cares about this except
mathematicians. It isn’t required to tell a compelling story, to articulate the
theory of consumer choice, or to test that theory.
Let’s look at another example from development theory. The
Harrod-Domar model is constructed from three equations that describe the
natural growth rate, the warranted growth rate and the actual growth rate. Once
thus equipped, it discusses what happens when the warranted growth rate exceeds
the natural growth rate, and vice versa. Seems fine, but the problem is that
the math does nothing for the model. Indeed, it actually makes it harder to
understand. The insight or hypothesis in the model is that sustained growth
requires harmony between the growth of capital and the growth of the labour
force that uses it (and their skill level). If capital abundance grows slower
than labour abundance then structural unemployment emerges, as it does in most
developing countries. If capital grows faster than labour then liquidity
becomes abundant and the price of labour is bid up, as we see in many developed
countries. I think there is probably some way to improve this story with math,
but the maths in the Harrod-Domar model doesn’t make it clearer or more
testable.
Now admittedly, sometimes putting things into a
mathematical form provides important insights. For example, the basic
microeconomic model of individual utility maximisation allows for the
development of an increasingly complicated graphical representation of the
economy that provides insights into why markets clear, why prices move the way
they do and why pareto efficiency emerges, among many other things, that would
be very difficult to articulate with words. Indeed, the core of microeconomics
is marginal theory, which is fundamentally inextricable from calculus.
In cases where mathematisation doesn’t initially lead to
new insights it might still lead eventually to a statistically testable
hypothesis. Arguably, hypotheses expressed in largely non-mathematical forms
can also give rise to forms accessible to statistics, but more mathematically
articulated models tend to garner more precise answers from the data. For
example, if you ask people ‘do you hate your job’, you can only get a binary
answer. If you ask people instead to rate their job satisfaction on a scale of
1-10 and define <5 as being ‘dissatisfied’ you get a richer answer to your
question.
Mathematics is also the language of logic, and stating
hypotheses in a logically manipulable form is critical to the development of
theory. But here it must be remembered that putting a theory into a
mathematical form rather than sticking to linguistic logic frequently involves
a simplification. For example, trade models certainly show, convincingly, that
openness to trade should lead to utility gains for all involved. But they do
not account for political or institutional factors, among other things,
arguably because these factors are too hard to crowbar into the model. As a
result, implementers of the ‘Washington consensus’ of trade-for-development overlooked
several critical issues, such as the fact that American and European markets
remained closed to African agricultural exports, and that corrupt elites in
African nations were likely to funnel proceeds away from development to foreign
accounts in order to enrich themselves. These issues were not lost on
development practitioners, but they couldn’t be captured in models because they
were too amorphous and therefore not amenable to a simple mathematical form.
This is not to say that simplification should always be
avoided, or that economics does a bad job of it. Simplification often allows
for certain key issues to float to the surface of an investigation. Economics
is also unusual in that it explicitly states its simplifying assumptions while
other disciplines have a tendency to act as though they haven’t made any
assumptions (such as liberal international relations theory). This is
especially important with regards to norms. Maths cannot engage in normative discussions.
This is a weakness of sorts, but it also means economists must be very explicit
when introducing a normative bias in favour of one outcome or another.
What all these arguments add up to is simply a word of
caution and a request for a bit more modesty. In recent years economics has
gotten a little bit carried away with the mathematics. It has frequently been
guilty of conflating mathematics with science. It has betrayed a failure to
understand the different between induction, which is what science does, and
deduction, which is what math does. Its emphasis on mathematical models has
made it much less accessible to a lay audience at a time when that audience has
been increasingly affected by the arguments of economists in the policy realm. Simplification
has given rise to some spectacular failures on the part of the discipline, the
most obvious being the self-correcting market hypothesis, which is great for
making mathematical models work but far from reality. Finally, economics’ love
affair with mathematics has occasionally resulted in a hubristic dismissal of
other disciplines, something we don’t want in this era of complexity.
Economics should not abandon mathematics or its push to
have other social sciences more fundamentally integrate mathematical techniques
into their own methods. Rather, it should become more cogent of the strengths
and weaknesses of mathematics compared to other analytical frameworks. As is so
often the case some wider training in the basics of the theory of knowledge
would be useful. They might then not conflate numbers with science or
simplification with insight and instead simply go about humbly testing their
clearly stated hypotheses—more than enough to set economics apart from other
disciplines at the present time, at least in Australia.
Comments
Post a Comment