These are two drafts for a presentation of
my thesis theme to a group of other PhD students. They were both overtime so I had to integrate and cut them down.
My PhD is
concerned with modelling happiness. My undergraduate degree was in philosophy,
and I am principally motivated by a desire to better integrate the philosophical
literature on this topic into the existing research stream, which is mostly
prosecuted by psychologists and economists. To date, academic happiness research,
which began in the early 70s, has been principally driven by empirics rather
than theory. This is understandable, because very little of what we mean by ‘happiness’
can be observed and measured. This is precisely why economics decided to focus
on utility instead and to utilise revealed preferences and rational actor
theory rather than something like the hedonic psychology model of behaviour. However,
I am little bit troubled by this approach as I think it sometimes risks overlooking
aspects of happiness that aren’t measurable. My hope is to develop a model of
happiness that is more integrative and expansive and then test it empirically.
Now as I just said, many of the hypotheses that I am interested in involve
unobservable factors like ‘meaningfulness’ and living ethically. I am currently
thinking of work arounds that will allow me to at least make a start on
empirical stuff, but today I thought I would talk more about the theory itself
and leave empirics to a future session.
Ui = log(WELLBEINGi) + HAPPINESSi + MEANINGi
I have a few
quick things to point out. The dependent variable is utility, measured cardinally rather than one a 1-10 scale; I
will return to this in a future session. The independent variables are all words that
have been used in the literature to mean utility. This is fitting, because
precisely what I am trying to do is integrate these different aspects or
sources of utility. Each of the independent variables refers to a cluster of
variables—this is a multi-level model in that sense—so wellbeing includes
things like income and companionship while meaning includes things like church
attendance and career advancement. Each of the three clusters corresponds very
roughly to one of the three literature groups: wellbeing to development
economics, happiness to psychology and meaning to philosophy (and psychiatry to
some extent).
Wellbeing is
predominantly about the absence of deprivation. I use the term wellbeing even
though psychologists mean something a bit different when they use wellbeing
because I can think of no better term to describe the ‘lack’ of negative
factors. You can think about it in terms of Maslow’s hierarchy of needs or in
terms of development economics, or indeed both. Some key components are income,
health, education, companionship and/or reproduction and capabilities in the
sense that Amartya Sen uses in his definition of development as freedom or
agency.
Wellbeing is
in log form because we have a lot of evidence that these items, especially
income, suffer from diminishing returns to happiness. However, a seminal paper
by Wolfers and Stevenson showed that income and happiness have a very tight
linear fit on the log scale. Theoretically, we can understand this as
reflecting the fact that having all the prerequisites for agency and
self-actualisation is only half the puzzle—the other half is actually being
able to self-actualise. Getting more ability to self-actualise doesn’t have
much effect once you’ve already secured the ability.
Let me immediately
pause here. I don’t want to give the impression that I have an agenda to show that
self-actualisation is what matters. I used to think that but I abandoned that
hypothesis years ago. It is quite possible to be supremely happy enjoying, for
example, a life full of leisure, or video games for that matter. The model
allows for that, but it also captures things like identity and
self-actualisation, which aren’t really allowed for in hedonic models,
set-point theory or the naïve income-driven models of happiness beloved of
neoclassical development economics (which is not to say that I am not fond of
those models).
Happiness is
an exogenous shock variable modelled as an auto-regressive process. It is not
captured by any sub-variables because the potential sources of these shocks are
too broad and vary widely depending on what time scale you are using. For
example, at the hourly time scale things like missing the bus or finding a
dollar matter, while at the annual time scale we are more interested in things
like divorce and promotions. This part of the literature draws heavily on studies
in psychology concerning adaptation, homeostasis and set point theory. The crux
of this research is that, arguably, human neurochemistry is characterised by
homeostatic theory, which suggests that we have a natural base line happiness
of say, 7/10 on a 1-10 scale. While we may experience divergences from this
set-point owing to events like orgasm or the death of a spouse, over time we
always converge back to the set-point.
The final
cluster is meaning. This is the part that we don’t see much in the existing
literature. Yet In the religious and philosophical literature we see a strong emphasis
on the idea that meaning is critical for sustained
happiness, which is part of why I am concerned with it: meaning might be a
channel for overcoming homeostasis or permanently elevating the set-point. For
example, one of the core tenets of Buddhism is that all life is suffering because,
in an existential sense, because we can never sate our desires, and that asceticism
is the escape hatch from this situation. Schopenhauer formalised this
philosophy in the 19th century. His pupil, Nietzsche, said that ‘man
needs a reason for his suffering’ and began the development of a theory of how
this reason can be created by the individual rather than received from the
universe, which is the fundamental idea of the monotheistic religions of Islam,
Judaism and Christianity, which find there apex philosophical representation in
the work of Soren Kierkegaard. Nietzsche’s theory was further developed by the
existentialists in the first half of the 20th Century, especially
Simone De Beauvoir.
To summarise
this theory very briefly, In order to be robustly and sustainably happy at a
high level, the individual needs to answer three questions: who am I, what
should I do and what is right? These are the questions of identity, motivation
and ethics. Along with ‘where am I’ they are collectively referred to as the
questions of being. Once the individual has come up with authentic answers,
which means that they are their own answers rather than answers received from
society, peers or religion, the individual then needs to go out and affirm
those authentic values. In so doing,
they will reveal to themselves, in and through their actions, to be the person
they believe themselves to be and that they want to be. This is known as the
coincidence of being, and is regarding in this philosophy as the end goal of
the human condition and the means of its transcendence. I can’t go into any
more detail here, but I do want to mention that inauthentic actualisation is
referred to as bad faith, and that one can be authentically religious even
though religion is an externally received value set, as evinced perhaps most
clearly by Martin Luther.
My first
paper elaborates this theory in much greater depth; my other two papers will
try to test elements of it empirically.
SECOND DRAFT
SECOND DRAFT
My PhD is concerned with modelling happiness. I have three
principal motivations.
The first is to better incorporate insights from philosophy
and, to a lesser extent, psychiatry, into the theoretical models of happiness we
currently use.
To date, academic research into happiness has been principally
driven by economists and psychologists, starting in the 1970s, and by empirics
rather than theory. You take a small question, like what happens to happiness
on weekends, and then check it against some data.
For two reasons, this approach is very appropriate as
compared to what came before.
First, theory doesn’t become knowledge unless you test it and
so we need to focus on things we can test—the old theories of happiness aren’t
readily amenable to that procedure.
This leads to the second reason, which is that happiness is
extremely difficult to measure and so you are limited in how grand a hypothesis
you can test.
However, I worry that at times this approach has meant that
we conflate the happiness we can measure for the totality of what comprises
happiness. I will give a few examples.
First, when we ask people ‘how happy are you right now?’ we
are principally measuring subjective
wellbeing, which is, speaking very simplistically, a mood state only
partially informed by general life circumstances. If someone finds a dollar in
the minutes before they are asked the question they report higher levels of
happiness than people who find nothing.
Psychologists, notably the hedonic school, are fascinated by
these phenomena.
However, we can intuitively grasp the idea that someone who
is poor, lonely and beset by failure who finds a dollar will be less happy than
someone who is rich, popular and successful who does not find a dollar. This
intuition suggests another element of happiness that we might call life satisfaction.
Economics is, I would say, generally more interested in life
satisfaction; hence its inclination towards objective measures of development
like income and capabilities.
Finally, you have probably come across, in yourself, in
literature or among your peers, the phenomenon of someone who has all the
prerequisites for happiness yet appears stuck in a kind of existential rut.
They might be struggling to answer the questions of being.
These are: ‘who am I’ (the identity question), ‘what should I do’ (the question
of purpose) and ‘what is right’ (the ethical question)? There is also ‘where am
I’ (the question of world). You might have heard of Robin Sharma, of Oprah
Winfrey fame. He was a billionaire hedge fund manager but famously sold his Ferrari
and became a monk in order to find ‘a more meaningful existence’.
Philosophy and theology made enormous theoretical inroads
into this group of issues in the late 19th and early 20th
centuries in the works of people like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Simone de
Beauvoir, but the happiness literature seems stuck on Aristotle 2000 years
earlier, and Bentham, who was hardly a philosopher of the good life.
Speaking very generally, it is these three aspects of
happiness that I would like to integrate into one model. I will present it next
time.
So that covers my first motivation—to better integrate
philosophy and to create a model that captures all the different sources of utility. I say utility because we
typically think of utility as a cardinal concept while happiness is almost
invariably measured on an ordinal scale, usually 1-10.
This brings me to my second motivation, which is to
investigate the possibility of re-scaling.
One of the most puzzling findings in the happiness
literature is that a goat-herder in the foothills of Pakistan is as happy
(7/10) as a young middle class Briton in London. The existing explanations for
this phenomenon are reference group effects and adaptation to a set-point.
Reference group effects owe their origins to the fact that
humans are a social species and we typically compare our circumstances to those
around us. Basically, if I am rich my world standards but poor by the standards
of my immediate peers I will feel poor and this will make me sad.
The goat herder in Pakistan does not have the same reference
group as the young Englishman. He is rich by his local standards while the boy
is poor.
Adaptation refers to the fact that we ‘get used to’ things,
or at least we seem to.
One of the most famous papers in this literature is a study
by Brickman and Coates in 1971 of lottery winners and paraplegics. They found that these individuals initially
experienced spikes and dips in their happiness immediately after the wins and
accidents. However, after two years their happiness had converged back to 7/10.
This is adaptation and 7/10 is the set-point.
There is some evidence to suggest that there are some things
we don’t completely adapt to. They include marriage and the death of a spouse.
One aspect of adaptation that was mentioned in the early
days of that literature but seems to have recently fallen by the wayside,
perhaps because of measurement issues, is that rather than adaptation, people
are actually just changing their scales—7/10 no longer means what it used to
mean.
Let me explain with a diagram:
We may see set-point phenomena but that doesn’t mean the set
point hasn’t shifted up or down.
Critically, if we think in terms of cardinal utility rather
than ordinal happiness we might get a clearer picture, at least a clearer
theoretical picture, of these issues. This is because ordinal happiness essentially
imposes a set point rather than allowing for, say, an Auto-regressive process with
structural breaks.
As I mentioned, this phenomena is extremely difficult to
identify empirically, but I have some leads that I will share in the future.
My final motivation is to better account for preferences in
happiness modelling. I am a little bit surprised by how little economists have
discussed this dimension.
For the most part, happiness regressions are estimated on
very large samples and the average parameters noted. We find in such studies,
among other things, that church attendance makes people happy.
Yet it seems intuitive that this result would only hold for
people who have faith. An atheist like me might find church a less than
pleasant experience. I would like to test whether average effects hold across
sub-samples of people with different preference sets.
They very well might, or some might at least. For example,
we might find that money has sharp diminishing returns even if you are a
materialist.
As well as looking at the impact of circumstances on
happiness given certain preferences, I would like to investigate the effect of
preferences on happiness given certain circumstances.
In initial research on this angle I am going to use HILDA,
which is Australia’s longitudinal panel. Its first wave includes question about
preference: how important is financial security, family, religion, community,
career etc. to you? I can use these questions to sort people into groups.
In the long run, I would like to get a better picture of
people’s preferences. In particular, I would like to find preferences in a
trade-off form i.e. who not only values career but would be willing to
sacrifice family to that end. Such data would open up a lot of interesting avenues.
There is some literature on how to infer preferences from
longitudinal data that I hope will furnish me something adequate.
In tackling this preferences stuff I am going to be
referring to the existentialist philosophy I mentioned earlier, psychology
literature on self-actualisation and human striving and basic economic theory.
I will discuss this stuff in greater detail next time.
Thanks.
Comments
Post a Comment