I had a comment on one of my pieces recently:
“I'm curious, why do you
think "maximum equity" should be a goal of Australian (or any other)
society? I know that inequality is a popular buzzword at the moment; watch
Q&A for more than a few minutes and someone is bound to mention it. But I
rarely if ever hear anyone enunciate why societies should pursue this end. It
is seems like an unspoken assumption that "equity" is a good
in-and-of itself.
It seems like one could make a pragmatic argument for increasing equity. For instance, where inequity is great there tends to be serious poverty at the lower extreme. Serious poverty, in a society where there is also affluence, can lead to increased crime. So if you want to decrease crime then increasing equity might be a solution. But then this could also be achieved by lifting the lower extremes without bringing down the higher extremes.
I don't really see anyone making this argument though. What tends to be voiced is either a flat assertion that "inequity is bad because... inequity", or else an appeal to emotion. "Don't you care that people are poor/disenfranchised/in need?" We might call this the 'empathy argument'. The problem with this line is that assumes that plight of the least well off confers a moral responsibility on everyone else. And as philosophical grounds go this is far more shaky than I think people realise.”
I have just finished teaching a module on inequality in
China which covered a lot of this material, so I thought I write up a
generalised response.
To start, I must address the ‘maximum equity’ point by
emphasising that maximum equity does not mean perfect equity. I made that
comment in the context of trade-offs between efficiency and equity. There are
good reasons for tackling inequality, as I will outline below, and so if there
is no cost to doing so we should proceed with tackling it. However, there are
usually trade-offs to tackling it, also discussed below, so we need to weigh
the costs and benefits.
I will start with the arguments for addressing inequality,
then the counterarguments, and then discuss how to operationalise this stuff in
public policy.
Arguments for why equity is important can be classified
into two broad categories—intrinsic and instrumental. Intrinsic arguments
concern why inequality is bad in and of itself. Instrumental arguments suggest
that inequality should be avoided because it leads to negative contingent
outcomes, like crime, low growth or social dislocation.
In my opinion, the instrumental arguments for why
inequality is bad are quite weak, especially in terms of the empirical evidence
for them, whereas the intrinsic arguments are quite strong. I will consequently
start with the instrumental arguments, and keep the discussion brief.
The most comprehensive analysis of the instrumental
arguments against inequality is The
Spirit Level by Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett. This book has
subsequently came under intense criticism, notably by Christopher Snowden in The Spirit Level Delusion. I think it is
worth noting that even staunch advocates of instrumental arguments against
inequality, like Andrew Leigh, don’t think The
Spirit Level is very good. Its analysis mostly consists of correlations not
causal relationships, and their data appears cherry picked on occasion. You can
access a lot of Snowden’s takedowns here: http://spiritleveldelusion.blogspot.com.au/ and
here http://www.wsj.com/articles/SB127862421912914915.
Leaving aside the data, the theoretical arguments are at
least reasonable. I’ll only cover a few big ones here:
Inequality
leads to lower growth. There are typically two conduits for this
effect. The first involves poor people not being able to save as much, thereby
depressing investment, which reduces capital accumulation and slows growth. The
second is that poor people can’t invest in mobility in the form of education,
health and transport, which depresses human capital formation and thereby,
productivity.
This argument recently drew some support from an IMF study.
I was at a seminar last week on a paper that basically debunked the IMF study.
I can’t link to the paper because it is forthcoming. Statistical evidence
suggests that the effect the IMF observes is a poverty effect, not an
inequality effect. If you are impoverished, you can’t save or invest in human
capital, and this weakens growth. But you can be relatively poor in a rich but unequal society like the United
States and still be able to save and invest.
Inequality
undermines democracy. Stiglitz makes this argument at length in The Price of Inequality. He suggests
that the very wealthy can co-opt the political process through lobbying and the
financing of political campaigns, skewing outcomes to favour them rather than
the broad mass off the public. Recent empirical research suggesting that
legislation in the US resembles Oligarchic outcomes corroborates this argument.
What’s less clear is whether the channel is inequality or some breakdown in the
institutional structures of the United States. Would greater equality fix this?
Similar analysis needs to be conducted for more equal states before we can draw
a clearer conclusion.
China provides some interesting case data for this argument
(albeit a more generalised form concerned with social unrest rather than
democracy). Since reform and opening up under Deng, inequality has shot up in
China, but poverty has also plummeted. Protests and other instances of
instability and disaffection have risen proportionally to inequality,
suggesting a relationship. It gets weird when you see that the Communist Party
is doing a lot about it though, which suggests that inequality only foments
unrest until that unrest because political salient, at which point the ruling
class acts on it. In China’s case decisively, and I think we’re about to see
relatively decisive action in the West as well (if we aren’t already).
Inequality
leads to crime, bad health and social dislocation. This
is the main argument made in The Spirit Level and the main one that has been
debunked. The data just don’t support it. The causation is deeper. I certainly
think things like public education, health and transport help, but it’s not
clear why.
Those are the main instrumental arguments. I don’t find
them very convincing, but maybe I haven’t presented them as robustly as
possible. I turn now to the intrinsic arguments, which I find thoroughly
convincing.
The first intrinsic argument comes from utilitarianism.
Theory and empirical evidence suggests diminishing marginal returns to income
for happiness. That means that a dollar is worth more in terms of happiness to
a poor person than a rich person. Ergo, taking a dollar from a rich person and
giving it to a poor person increases the total utility of the population.
The second intrinsic argument, one that even staunch
defenders of inequality like Hayek acknowledged, is that life outcomes are
substantially determined by the genetic lottery and one’s birth class. That is
to say, a large part of the reason why someone is rich or poor has to do with
luck rather than effort. It seems unjust for some to be condemned to a life of
relative scarcity by accident, so there is an argument for redistribution, especially
insofar as it relates to equality of opportunity (i.e. equal access to
transport, jobs, education and health).
The third intrinsic argument is similar. It says that we
are all human and so have at least a close-to equal claim to collective
resources. This argument is about enhancing cooperation within the species,
whereas arguments in favour of inequality tend to be about encouraging
individual achievement. Both are important for our survival.
The final intrinsic argument for equality is that people
care about it. As my commenter said, some people take it on assumption that
equity is good. Recent research in evolutionary biology suggests that this is
wired into our genes to help us compete as a group against other groups. While
selfish people outcompete altruistic people within groups, groups with more
altruists outcompete groups with relatively more selfish people at the group
level. It is thus important to have people wired for collectivist values. Inequality
thus makes a large number of people unhappy—it incenses them. There is
therefore a reason to act on it, even if there is no instrumental reason for
doing so. I should stress that these people do not want perfect equality, but
surveys of the kinds of income distributions that people would be satisfied
with always show preferred distributions that widely diverge from actual
distributions. The free ebook Thinking About Inequality
reports a lot of this data.
That covers off the argument for taking action against
inequality. What about the argument against taking action? These tend to take
two forms: the first is property-rights, the second is disincentive effects.
The rights-based argument is that people are entitled to
their property. Taxing them for redistribution purposes (as opposed to Pigovian
taxes or the funding of public goods like defence) is thus basically a kind of
theft. Ironically, this was the first rights-based argument ever advanced, long
before rights became a vehicle for social justice, their language was used by
aristocrats to defend their privileges.
A related and in some ways stronger argument is the ‘just
desserts’ principle. This argument, which is well made by Mankiw in his paper ‘Defending
the 1 per cent’, is that people are entitled to what they earn. If you work you
but off to get qualified as a doctor and then work your butt off to earn a
bunch of money as a doctor, the government shouldn’t come in to redistribute
your earnings to someone who doesn’t go to all that effort.
In his book The
Righteous Mind, psychologist Jonathan Haidt provides empirical evidence
that both left and right-wing people care deeply about inequality. However, right-wing
individuals have a just-desserts concept of inequality, which means that they
see unemployment benefits as unfair rather than equity-enhancing. In contrast,
the left emphasises relative inequality and sees unemployment benefits (among
other welfare payments) as critical to equity. No wonder our politics is so
fractious.
Just desserts is related to the third argument against
taking action on inequality, which is the disincentive effects. If you tax
someone when they work, they will be discouraged from working. In the extreme
case, they will instead opt to receive transfer payments instead.
The formal articulation of this idea is the Mirrlees model
in economics. Therein, everyone has a level of productivity, W, and a level of
effort E. Their output is ExW. If the government taxes high productivity
individuals and transfers some of their output to low-productivity individuals,
it creates an incentive for high-productivity individuals to hide their
productivity by exerting less effort and either being taxed less as a result or
receiving a transfer payment. The result is less wealth overall. This situation,
where redistribution results in less total money to go round, is referred to by
economists as ‘Okun’s leaky bucket’.
Now in recent times we have found that disincentive effects
are not as strong as many people think. Marginal tax rates only seem to kick in
around 70%. Up until that point, the status effect of being middle class keeps
people working and chasing promotions rather than settling into a cushy dole-bludging
lifestyle. Tax evasion by corporations seems similarly inelastic at the top end
because high-tech and advanced firms need to attract very highly qualified
talent and that talent wants to live in nice, developed places like Copenhagen.
The leaky bucket also doesn’t have legs in the context of
wealth taxes like capital gains and inheritance tax. There is no effort
involved in making money off existing wealth, so there can’t be much of a
disincentive effect to taxing it. That said, tax cuts to the rich often result
in increases in total tax receipts because people take their money out of
low-interest, tax free state securities and put them into more productive
assets that are taxed.
How to operationalise all this? Libertarians like Mankiw
would argue that tax should only be collected to pay for public goods (i.e.
non-rival and non-excludable) like street lights and defence, and to offset
externalities like pollution. In other cases, things should be left to the
market. Implicit in this argument is the notion of market justice: in a pure
market, the person who wants a good the most is willing to pay the most for it.
The problem with this line of argument is that if people have unequal wealth then
the person who wants a good the most might not be able to pay the most for it.
There is also the issue of the genetic lottery, human rights and utility
enhancement.
That said, perfect equality is not desirable either. Such a
system discourages innovation and basically results in an equal share of
poverty. So there must be some balance, and this balance requires value
judgements.
This is what I was on about in my post that was commented
on. When designing public policy, we can start by picking the low-hanging
fruit, which means trying to get as much easy efficiency and equity as possible
before making value judgements. An example is the Australian superannuation
system as opposed to the old defined benefit scheme or the ludicrous American
model. Defined benefits are too generous and inefficient while the American pension
system leaves too many people without retirement benefits. The Australian model
is both efficient and equitable. After you’ve picked this low-hanging fruit,
then it is up to the public to determine how the rest of the cookie crumbles—more
progressive publics will push more equity (e.g. in Scandinavia), more
libertarian publics will push for more efficiency (e.g. in America). An example
is the HECS system for funding university education in Australia. There is a subsidy
for course fees in this system. How large that subsidy is gets determined by
public values. But before this determination, the system already picked the low
hanging equity and efficiency fruits by employing income-contingent loans and
the tax system to manage repayment.
There is a lot more that I could write, but I think this is enough.
Comments
Post a Comment