Review of book by this title by Carol Graham
Carol Graham is at the forefront of the movement to bridge
economics, public policy and the growing literature on wellbeing and its
determinants. This book is a substantial step forward in that endeavour. It
presents innovative work using wellbeing metrics to provide new insights into
long-running questions in economics and public policy around inequality,
welfare and mobility. It is particularly outstanding in this literature for two
reasons. First, it is aware of the limitations inherent in much wellbeing data
and utilizes clever techniques to avoid many of them. Second, rather than
staying entirely within wellbeing metrics, it instead uses these metrics
specifically and deliberately to explore underlying drivers of economic
phenomena like discount rates, education decisions and crime rates.
Before discussing the insights of the book, it’s necessary
to discuss data for a moment. The admissibility of wellbeing data has been a
controversial issue at least since Easterlin first questioned the “more income
= more utility” assumption using wellbeing data in 1974. Early criticisms
pertained to the capacity of such data to parse long-term evaluative wellbeing
out from shorter-term emotional moods, as well as to the large effects that
priming had on responses to subjective wellbeing questions. In particular,
people’s responses could be substantially influenced by asking them about
negative things like politics before asking them about their subjective
wellbeing, or by manipulating them with seemingly inconsequential factors like
finding a dollar before the interview (Gilbert 2006). What dimensions of life
mattered to people’s evaluative wellbeing could also be influenced by priming.
For example, asking about dating in subjective wellbeing surveys has been shown
to significantly increase the importance people place on their romantic
entanglements when considering their wellbeing relative to control groups who
are not asked about dating.
Graham was a member of the National Academy of Sciences
Panel on Well-being metrics for Public Policy from 2011–2012 and is also a
scientific advisor to the Gallup organisation, which collects the World Values
Survey, one of the principle sources of wellbeing data used by researchers. She
is very much across the criticisms of wellbeing data, and has been a central
part of efforts to address them during data collection. For example, life
satisfaction surveys now typically include several questions that allow
different dimensions of wellbeing like satisfaction and mood to be teased apart.
The questions are also located in surveys in positions where they are unlikely
to be affected by questions that come before them. Some noise will still creep
into responses. For example, if someone is having a bad day—perhaps they missed
the bus before the survey—this will result in most cases in them giving lower
responses, even to questions that request a long-term evaluation of life
satisfaction. However, the Gallup data sets used in Graham’s book contain
thousands of observations. The distribution of these biases throughout survey
responses can thus reasonably be expected to match the distribution of the
relevant events in the day to day life of respondents. As such, they’re not
really a problem.
One issue does remain, which is concerns about scale-norming
(Fredrick & Loewenstein 1999, pg. 308). This is where the qualitative
meaning of different points on a respondent’s scales changes over time. For
example, for a graduate student, completing their PhD might be what they think
is needed for them to reach 9/10, while getting a tenure-track position at a
top 200 university is what they need to be 10/10 (their ‘best possible life’).
However, when they do get that tenure track position, their horizons
necessarily push outward, and now their 10/10 is getting to Professor. As such,
someone could give a 9/10 in two consecutive waves even though their own
assessment is that their life is getting better. They simply can’t communicate
that within the strictures of the scale instrument.
Scale norming is a problem for wellbeing research that
needs much more investigation, and it does raise concerns about some of the
discussion in this book. However, a great deal of Graham’s analysis sidesteps
scale-norming worries. For starters, the focus of the book is the badly-off.
These people have a huge amount of space in their scale responses to improve
into, as it were—they don’t need to rescale. Second, Graham makes ingenious use
of data about dimensions of affective wellbeing that are either not measured on
a scale, like the number of times someone smiled yesterday, or where it is
reasonable to assume that the affective phenomenon in question does exist on a
scale, such as someone’s stress burden. These data are used to check the
robustness of the scale data, and also provide their own insights. Finally,
Graham focuses on questions that can be examined using broad correlations in
the data. For these, the suggestive evidence provided by wellbeing metrics is
sufficient to provide a rudimentary test of hypotheses, especially as those
hypotheses are fairly intuitive; for example, that people who are hopeful about
the future invest in it while those who are hopeless have much higher discount
rates.
The central claim of the book is that hope matters. More
formally, “the Gatsby curve in opportunities has an additional beliefs and
behaviours channel that may perpetuate and deepen inequality over time.” The
Gatsby curve shows a correlation between inequality as measured by the gini
coefficient and intergenerational economic mobility. As inequality rises,
mobility falls. Graham’s book illuminates several new mechanisms that drive
this relationship.
The first of these is that stress has differential impacts
on the wealthy and the poor, or rather, that the poor and the wealthy experience
different kinds of stress and this conditions their behaviour. ‘Good stress’ is
associated with goal pursuit, while ‘bad stress’ emerges out of desperation.
Individuals who expend a large amount of cognitive energy on contemplating
bills and how to secure food have little leftover for long-term planning. They
sometimes consequently engage in economically irrational behaviour.
The second, related mechanism is that beliefs about the
long-term benefits of hard work affect how much effort people expend in the
present. Graham notes that inequality can be a source of individual effort and
economic dynamism when it reflects the fact that people can get ahead if they
work hard. However, when inequality instead reflects the fact that institutions
and incentives favour the already privileged it has a dampening effect on both
effort and dynamism. People at the bottom of the distribution develop a sense
of hopelessness and consequently disconnect from the economy. Data about
people’s attitudes to hard work from the Gallup World Values survey suggest
that Americans, especially white former manufacturing workers, are becoming
increasingly sceptical that hard work can secure the American dream and are
consequently engaging in short-sighted activities like opioid abuse.
A final mechanism that receives substantial attention in
the book is that the poor often face higher opportunity costs to attain basic
goods than the rich. A notable example is that the bureaucracies that
administer universal welfare programs like Medicaid are considerably more
efficient and user-friendly than welfare programs that are strictly for the
poor. An incisive anecdote in this regard is that the penalties for selling a
food stamp for cash are around the same as those for manslaughter and sexual
contact with a child under 12.
There are a range of other very interesting themes in the
book, including how wellbeing and optimism about the future differ across
racial groups in America, how cultural differences in attitudes towards work
and fairness can affect behaviour, and how mechanisms for coping with stress
and insecurity differ across social classes. These are all insights that bear not
only on aspects of economic policy concerning welfare and mobility, but also on
the core business of economics, namely predicting human behaviour in a
parsimonious manner. The principle merit of Graham’s work is in this
demonstration that wellbeing theory and metrics, even in their present infancy,
have a lot to contribute to economics and economic policy and deserve to be
taken more seriously. Happiness for All not
only presents Graham’s original work in this area, but also does an excellent
job of succinctly summarising what ideas in the wellbeing literature are most
readily adaptable for these purposes.
Overall, Happiness for All is a great read for anyone who
demands quantitative methods but also recognises that inequality and social
mobility have substantial qualitative and normative dimensions. It is timely in
the aftermath of Trump’s election, which many have attributed to feelings of
hopelessness and desperation among large segments of America’s population,
especially in the rust belt states. It will also be useful to people looking
for policy responses to the loss of hope in America, as the final chapter deals
specifically with wellbeing-literate ways to rekindle the American dream.
References
Easterlin, R. (1974), ‘Does economic growth improve the
human lot? Some empirical evidence’, in David and Reder eds. Nations and households in economic growth:
essays in honour of Moses Abramovitz, New York, NY: Academic Press
Frederick, S. and Loewenstein, G. (1999), ‘Hedonic
Adaptation’, in Kahneman, Diener and Schwarz (eds.), Well-being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, New York, NY:
Russell Sage Foundation
Gilbert, D. (2006), ‘Stumbling on happiness: ‘, London, UK:
Harper Perennial
Comments
Post a Comment